Monday, May 27, 2013
More On Grad School in Philosophy
There's an interesting thread on Brian Leiter's blog having to do with advice for new grad students. Some of the advice seems apt for non-philosophy grad students and for those thinking of going to grad school.
Saturday, May 11, 2013
Are you thinking about going to grad school in philosophy?
Tuesday, May 7, 2013
Ross and Prima Facie Duties
**This is from guest blogger, Dylan.**
I ultimately completely agree with Ross on his view of prima facie duties. I think the most compelling part is that there is a non absolutist view to it. Morals are not simple enough that one code will work for every choice we have to make in life. There are times when feelings will be hurt by the choices we make, that is unavoidable I think Ross has a good system here to minimize the pain placed on people. There is no set in stone way to determine whether or not an action is immoral that I feel is illogical and Ross does a great job combating it. I completely agree with the idea that sometimes within different situations you have to have a guideline for how to make the best choice morally. This does not say this is how it will work every time just simply a way to help guide your decisions along and that is why I agree with him.
I think that an argument from the Utilitarians would focus on the fact that this is not an absolute argument. I feel the Utilitarians focus on there needing to be an absolute way to determine a moral decision. I think that Utilitarians would argue that their view is also for breaking promises if more good comes from it then harm, this in turn would still state to be a utilitarian view. They would contest that the duties that Ross speaks of should be broken if it means causing more ultimate good and that there has to be one simple way to make a moral decision. Like I have said I agree with Ross on his prima facie duties but I don't think he would convert any Utilitarians on the basis that its not an absolute view. anyone have any thoughts?
I ultimately completely agree with Ross on his view of prima facie duties. I think the most compelling part is that there is a non absolutist view to it. Morals are not simple enough that one code will work for every choice we have to make in life. There are times when feelings will be hurt by the choices we make, that is unavoidable I think Ross has a good system here to minimize the pain placed on people. There is no set in stone way to determine whether or not an action is immoral that I feel is illogical and Ross does a great job combating it. I completely agree with the idea that sometimes within different situations you have to have a guideline for how to make the best choice morally. This does not say this is how it will work every time just simply a way to help guide your decisions along and that is why I agree with him.
I think that an argument from the Utilitarians would focus on the fact that this is not an absolute argument. I feel the Utilitarians focus on there needing to be an absolute way to determine a moral decision. I think that Utilitarians would argue that their view is also for breaking promises if more good comes from it then harm, this in turn would still state to be a utilitarian view. They would contest that the duties that Ross speaks of should be broken if it means causing more ultimate good and that there has to be one simple way to make a moral decision. Like I have said I agree with Ross on his prima facie duties but I don't think he would convert any Utilitarians on the basis that its not an absolute view. anyone have any thoughts?
Friday, May 3, 2013
Kant’s Deontology—questions regarding contradictions in the Principle of Universalizability
**This is from guest blogger, Danny W.**
Alright, here begins my attempt to say
something intelligent about Kant’s Deontology—a tall order indeed. I’ll lay
some groundwork first to review what we know. Kant proposed his ethical
doctrine, deontology, as a moral guide which suggests doing only those actions
in which an individual acts out of intrinsically ‘good will’—or to fulfill some
objective duty. Hence, Kant would say that acting with the motivation to
exercise good will, and conversely, to have goodness of will be the only end
sought, would garner the highest moral praise. In connection with these claims,
Kant did not ultimately think the consequence of an action played a role in the
moral evaluation of someone’s action—the evaluation would center around the
motivation or intention of performing the action. One question that naturally
arises surrounding Kant’s ethical system is: How do we know when someone is
acting out of good will? As the kind, thoughtful philosopher that he was, Kant
made sure to provide several tests. I plan to focus on the Principle of
Universalizability—one of Kant’s litmus tests for determining whether actions
are moral or immoral.
A quick aside before we continue with
the Principle of Universalizability. Another test in his deontology (which
roughly means the “study of duty”) is the “Principle of Humanity” test.
Despite
the potential confusion surrounding which actions are actually done as ‘means’
versus ‘ends’—the definitions of which remain elusive in certain hypothetical
scenarios—I think the principle boils down to respecting and caring for fellow
human beings. Sure there are flaws, and Kant didn’t state it so abruptly, but
that seems to be the gist of his thinking. There may be holes, but I will not
focus on this test any further.
The Principle of Univeralizability, on
the other hand, is a three step process which allows any person to judge
whether an action is moral or immoral. (1) Formulate a maxim, rule, law, or
state of things, (2) universalize the maxim (i.e., imagine that everyone in the
world is following maxim), and (3) assess
whether there is a contradiction in the hypothetical world from part (2).
If there is a contradiction, then the action described in the maxim from step
(1) would be immoral, and vice versa.
My biggest concern with the PoU arises
when we speak about step (3)—deeming hypothetical worlds to be contradictory. It is interesting how
Kant uses this word, and confusing what he actually expects when someone is
using this test. It is common to think of contradictions in formal logic as
statements of the form A&~A (i.e., something, A, is true and false
simultaneously). Let’s try out our paradigm case: I want to cheat on my wife; I
imagine everyone in the world cheating as well; the result is a world in which
monogamous relationships cannot exist and the cheating could thus not logically
be called cheating. It seems like the only way you can report this
contradiction—in a strict logical sense—would be to assert that “cheating” (as
we know it in our real world) cannot
exist in our hypothetical world (in which the maxim is that everyone cheats
on significant other). However, it does not follow that just because everyone
cheats (in our hypothetical world) that the “action of cheating” is made impossible. Significant others will
still exist and one will cheat on that partner—the metaphysical circumstances
do not change between our real and hypothetical worlds. It is not as if there
is “cheating” and “not cheating” taking place in a metaphysical sense.
“Cheating” persists but our anthropocentric definition of cheating (sexual
interactions with a person A while you are simultaneously engaged in a
monogamous relationship with another person B) loses all meaning and
descriptive power. The word becomes hollow of meaning, since “monogamous
relationships” do not exist and thus our definition of “cheating”—inherently
built on the metaphysical status of monogamous relationships— from the real
world does not make sense and disintegrates. Thus, an action persists but we no
longer have the vocabulary to label the action—vocabulary we obviously do have in the real world. Okay this
might be major backtracking, but here goes. I suppose that through the lens of
the hypothetical world, we wouldn’t even regard the action as “cheating”. So,
Kant achieves his contraction based on a logical
contraction across worlds. I guess my previous thoughts had been focused on
having the contradiction occur in the same world—which didn’t make sense.
Part of my thinking was that Kant was
also using contradiction to generally state that there is a contradiction to our accepted social
structure and stability. If everyone is cheating, there is no more social
order as we know it in this world. These are just some of my trailing thoughts,
but I think I will open it up for comments. I’m interested to know how all of
you view the tests that Kant puts forth for his deontology!
Labels:
Deontology,
ethics,
Kant,
Principle of Universalizability
Rawls’ Veil of Ignorance—Do rational agents come to the same conclusions?
**This is from guest blogger, Danny W.**
In Theory of Justice, John Rawls presents
an argument outlining the most just forms of resource distribution. Rawls
devised a methodology for arriving at governing principles that delineate how a
just society ought to spread its resources to its constituents. Rawls describes
a hypothetical position—the Original Position (OP)—from which any rational
agent would arrive at the same common principles regarding how resources ought
to be distributed. The rational agents would be under a “veil of ignorance”
which effectively means that they would not yet be implanted into the future
society—for which they were determining principles of resource distribution—and
would not know their social or economic status in that future world. These
agents would then, from this veil of ignorance, be required to choose which
principles would bring about the society that would leave them best off (i.e., even
if the agent turned out to be on a lower socioeconomic rung, they would not be
too screwed). Rawls alleges that, given rational, self-interested agents, every
person would choose the following principles for resource distribution (as seen
on the handout):
First Principle: Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic
freedoms that are compatible with similar freedoms for others.
Second Principle: Social and economic inequalities are to
satisfy two conditions:
a. They are to be attached to offices and positions
open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity;
b. They are to be to the greatest benefit of the
least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).
However, I have questions about the
relationships between these ideal, rational agents, the OP, and the veil of
ignorance—okay, I also have questions regarding the principles that are
unanimously reached by these ‘veiled’ agents. I like the principles that Rawls
arrives at (because they seem to satisfy some brute intuitions that I have),
however I’m curious how his argument holds up under greater scrutiny.
My biggest criticism is of Rawls’ supposition
that all rational agents would converge on his 2nd principle
naturally and necessarily. I keep hearing the word rational—and agents
described as those working under rational thought processes—and for some reason
wonder how exactly Rawls is using these terms. The world reason (and all of its
derivatives) tends to get thrown around carelessly from time to time without
much consideration for linguistic meaning. So what I assume Rawls is saying is
that, given the chance to articulate a deductive argument in premise-conclusion
form, someone using this structured style of ‘reasoning’ would arrive at a
conclusion which mirrors his Principles.
I assume most rational agents would decide that
the 1st principle is rational, in the sense that one could provide
the following argument:
(1) We all want to have basic freedoms (life,
liberty, happiness, yada yada), regardless of socioeconomic status.
(2) Since we are all humans (the same general
entity), each person should have access—or the right—to basic freedoms.
(3) A right to basic freedoms is identical for
all people; the right is either met or not met for whichever ‘freedoms’ are
deemed ‘basic freedoms’.
(Co) Each person ought to have equal right to basic freedoms.
So, that
was a rough sketch of an argument for equal rights to basic freedoms. A
supporter of this conclusion would—for the sake of a strong rational
argument—need to add supplementary premises about the connection between
personhood and access to rights, either by appealing to happiness, the raw
materials of a meaningful life, social order, etc. as intrinsic goods and
necessary conditions to be met in the lives of human beings. Also, I realize
the conclusion also leaves out another wrinkle in the principle—namely,
regarding the rights to basic freedoms of others in equilibrium with our
own—which could be accounted for with more premises and elbow grease. Someone
else could probably do a better job fleshing that out, but the general argument
takes shape, and I can understand why a ‘rational’ being would land on the
conclusion—even this truncated version.
In
contrast, I don’t see why someone, for example, would land on the Difference Principle (part b of 2nd
Principle). I’ve tried to think of
rational arguments that would land on that conclusion, but I’m not really sure
how to voice these. It seems intuitive that these rational agents in the OP
would—not knowing which lot they would be cast—go for an Egalitarian set-up. If
I have my thinking cap on in that OP, I might realize that, if the society I’m
entering has resource constraints—and I think we’re being idealistic if we
don’t consider that—then I will realize that a small fraction of the population
will actually have sufficient resources. If I’m self-interested and rational, I
might realize that there is a better shot at having the minimum to survive if I
decide on a principle of resource distribution that emulates
Egalitarianism—equality for all. That way, if I do draw the short straw in life
(in terms of sheer quantity of resources allotted to me), and get born into a
hut in a rural town in India, then I’ll feel better about being helped up to
that equal standard. Even if I end up being a stud running back for the Green
Bay Packers with boat-loads of ‘earned’ money, I would still have an equal cut
of the pie after all of the resource confiscations take place—I’d be surviving!
In retrospect as that Packer star, I would likely hate my decision, but from
the OP I would be making the best choice given the knowledge of how resources
naturally land in a society.
I’m not
sure Rawls has an answer to this. Okay, I’m sure he does and I will go and look
for it, but I’m curious to know what all of you think about these ramblings! Is
it possible to say which principles a rational agent or agents in the OP would
select? What about complications that arise when you start to realize the
possible disconnect between real society demands and the idealized test that
Rawls has carved out as a thought experiment? I’d love to hear any thoughts.
Ross on What Makes Right Acts Right
**This is from guest blogger, Cassy K.**
Briefly, Ross puts forth a non-absolutist theory revolving around prima fascia duties that are permanent but not always decisive. Those duties are fidelity, reparation, gratitude, justice, beneficence, non-maleficence, and self-improvement. He admits that this is not an exhaustive list, but each is necessary. In particular scenarios, some duties may be outweighed by others but they are always important regardless.
Shafer-Landau points out three primary difficulties with Ross's theory: 1. Arbitrariness: there's no apparent reason for why these particular duties are included. 2. Balancing: it's not clear why some duties take priority in certain cases, if they are not ranked. 3. how do we come to know these duties and the final duty to act on in specific cases?
While I think these are certainly good to point out, I personally don't think they're true objections. Each of them can simply be deduced to intuition. When you really think about it, why do we do anything? Regardless of what might be truly behind our actions, we do things because something (whatever that may be) compels us to do so. There are many days when I don't feel like going to work, but I still go. If I didn't find any compelling reason to go--even though I say I don't "want" to--I wouldn't. I think what we're discussing here is similar.
Presumably, Ross included these prima fascie duties because that's what his intuition instructed him to include. The only reason that we see this as a "difficulty" is because it's not as satisfying as we'd ideally like it to be. We dislike admitting that some things may happen by chance for the same reason--as human beings, "by chance" and "intuition" aren't satisfying answers, even if we make the majority of our decisions based on intuition. That's the reason that I decided to go to work even when I didn't feel like it, whereas my roommate often calls into work when she doesn't feel like going. We're wired differently; our decision-making is necessarily affected by our individual intuitions and dispositions. So while appealing to our intuitions might not be as ideal as a solid, empirical explanation, morality is not a science.
It would, of course, be nice if Ross's theory gave us a methodical way to calculate the absolute moral decision in every case. But given the complexity of the world, ourselves, and the decisions we face, is that even a feasible demand? I would argue that it absolutely is not--that when you really think about it, it's almost silly to ask. Utilitarianism is an interesting and thought-provoking theory, but the fact of the matter is that very little of that is actually going through my head when I'm contemplating a moral decision. I might be thinking about whether or not it will hurt or help others, but I'm not calculating hedons in my head. (Nevermind that I don't even know what that would look like in practice.)
I think Ross is onto something here. By focusing on what actually goes through our heads when we're making a moral decision and considering the complexities we face, he's conjured up something that actually seems to make sense in the real world as it really works, even if it hasn't allowed us to "close the book" on our discussion of morality.
Wednesday, May 1, 2013
Rawls and the Veil of Ignorance
**This is from guest blogger Cole, D.**
In his initial description
of the veil of ignorance and what it blocks out, Rawls makes an extensive
(although admittedly incomplete) list of the things that the person behind the
veil of ignorance does not know. A lot of them make perfect sense and help strengthen his argument. For example, he specifically says that the person
behind the veil does not have personality traits such as a penchant for
gambling. This helps strengthen the usage of the maximin principle; if the
person was wont to gamble recklessly and was allowed to have this quirk behind
the veil, they might opt to formulate a tyrannical society in hopes of landing
the top position.
However, I found one of the
elements of the veil that he cited to be problematic: “I assume that the
parties do not know the particular circumstances of their own society. That is,
they do not know its economic…situation or the level of civilization…it has been able to achieve,” (638). First of all, this seems wholly unnecessary. What
sort of effect would knowledge of one’s society have upon the entirely rational
person’s decision that would lead them to reject justice as fairness and the maximin
principle? It just seems odd that he would include this, but make no mention of
the agent’s knowledge of their gender being of any importance. This inclusion
seems to counter no objections and only cause problems. If the person behind
the veil had no knowledge of his or her society, they might decide upon a
heavily redistributive economic situation. In practice, this could be entirely
unfeasible. Consider a society in which food, knowledge, and general goods are bountiful
in nature and free for the taking, with a very low, very spread-out population
with a universally-practiced religion which dictates that its practitioners
only take as much as they need and never enslave others. In this society,
redistribution would be nonsensical; if anyone could take what they wanted
without negatively affecting anyone else, redistribution would do far more harm
than good. Note that I am not arguing against redistribution here—in fact, I am
generally highly in favor of it. However, Rawls’s inclusion of a limitation on societal
knowledge seems to be a definite flaw in his thought experiment, as some hypothetical societies would not benefit from it at all. I am interested
in if anyone was able to deduce a reason or come up with a defense for Rawls’s
inclusion of this counterexample.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)